Propositional Logic

This page defines propositional logic by instantiating the components of a logic defined as part of the generalities on logics. Propositional logic PL is the tuple (SymPL, ForPL, IntPL, ⊨PL) that we define piece by piece in later sections.

Syntax

Symbols

We define the set C = {¬, ∧, ∨, →, ↔} of logical connectors (all different from each others), the couple B = {(, )} of opening and closing parentheses (B is for brackets) disjoint from C, and an infinite set P disjoint from B and C whose members are called propositions.

Symbols of PL
The symbols of PL are SymPL = BCP.

We will write distinct propositions with distinct sequences of latin characters like so: A, P, ItsRaining, etc. Although ItsRaining is written with a sequence of 10 latin characters, it is counted as a single symbol in propositional logic.

Formulas

Formulas of PL

Formulas are recursively built as the smallest set ForPL such that:

  • for all x ∈ P, x ∈ ForPL;
  • for all φ ∈ ForPL, ¬φ ∈ ForPL;
  • for all φ, ψ ∈ ForPL, (φ ∧ ψ) ∈ ForPL;
  • for all φ, ψ ∈ ForPL, (φ ∨ ψ) ∈ ForPL;
  • for all φ, ψ ∈ ForPL, (φ → ψ) ∈ ForPL;
  • for all φ, ψ ∈ ForPL, (φ ↔ ψ) ∈ ForPL.
Atom
An atom is a formula that is reduced to a single proposition.

Note that we use a light shading on formulas in order to clearly distinguish them, in particular, when a formula is an atom, it makes it clear whether we are using the symbol in the context of a proposition or in the context of a formula.

By convention, the following operator precedence is assumed: ¬ has higher precedence than ∧; ∧ has higher precedence than ∨; and ∨ has higher precedence than → and ↔. As a result, it is possible to write formulas by leaving parentheses implicit. Therefore, the following formulas are considered well formed:

(A ∨ B) ∧ (B ∨ ¬B) → D implicitly meaning (((A ∨ B) ∧ (B ∨ ¬B)) → D)

ItIsRaining → ItIsWetOutside implicitly meaning (ItIsRaining → ItIsWetOutside)

In addition to these usual definitions that apply to any logic, we introduce special syntactic forms that are generally useful for algorithms.

Literal
A literal L is a formula that is either an atom (that is, L ∈ P) or the negation of an atom (that is, L = ¬P where P ∈ P).
Conjunctive normal form (CNF)
A formula φ ∈ ForPL is in conjunctive normal form (or CNF for short) if and only if φ = ψ1 ∧ … ∧ ψn for some n ∈ ℕ\{0} such that for all i ∈ {1, …, n}, there is p ∈ ℕ\{0} such that ψi = (Li,1 ∨ … ∨ Li,p), and Li,j are literals.

Put differently, a formula is in CNF if it is a conjunction of disjunction of literals.

Semantics

Interpretations

Interpretations in PL
An interpretation in PL is a function 𝓘 : P ⟶ {true, false}.

An interpretation simply says which propositions are considered true, and which ones are considered false.

We can define an interpretation 𝓘 such that 𝓘(ItIsRaining) = true and 𝓘(ItIsWetOutside) = false.

Satisfaction relation

Satisfaction relation in PL

An interpretation 𝓘 in PL satisfies a formula φ (that is, (𝓘, φ) ∈ ⊨PL, or 𝓘 ⊨PL φ) if and only if the following holds:

  • if φ is an atom, then 𝓘 ⊨PL φ iff 𝓘(φ) = true;
  • if φ = ¬ψ for some formula ψ, then 𝓘 ⊨PL φ iff 𝓘 ⊭PL ψ;
  • if φ = 1 ∧ ψ2) for some formulas ψ1 and ψ2, then 𝓘 ⊨PL φ iff 𝓘 ⊨PL ψ1 and 𝓘 ⊨PL ψ2;
  • if φ = 1 ∨ ψ2) for some formulas ψ1 and ψ2, then 𝓘 ⊨PL φ iff 𝓘 ⊨PL ψ1 or 𝓘 ⊨PL ψ2, or both;
  • if φ = 1 → ψ2) for some formulas ψ1 and ψ2, then 𝓘 ⊨PL φ iff 𝓘 ⊨PL ¬ψ1 or 𝓘 ⊨PL ψ2, or both;
  • if φ = 1 ↔ ψ2) for some formulas ψ1 and ψ2, then 𝓘 ⊨PL φ iff 𝓘 ⊨PL 1 → ψ2) and 𝓘 ⊨PL 2 → ψ1).

The interpretation 𝓘 of the previous example does not satisfy ItIsRaining → ItIsWetOutside. However, it satisfies ItIsRaining ∨ ItIsWetOutside as well as ¬ItIsWetOutside.

Note that given a finite theory T = {φ1, …, φn} and any formula ψ, it holds that T ⊨PL ψ if and only if {φ1 ∧ … ∧ φn}⊨PL ψ. This means that we can always replace a PL theory by a single formula. Therefore, we can assume that the relation ⊨PL is between formulas rather than between theories and formulas.

Properties of PL

PL is decidable and its complexity belongs to the class of NP-complete problems.

Given any formula φ, there exists a formula ψ in CNF such that φ ⊨PL ψ and ψ ⊨PL φ.

For any formulas φ, ψ ∈ ForPL, φ ⊨PL ψ if and only if φ → ψ is a tautology.

Deductive system

An example of a deductive system for PL that is both correct and complete can be defined as follows:

The deductive system SF0

The deductive system SF0 = (A0, R0) such that:

  • for all formulas φ, ψ, χ ∈ ForPL, A0 contains the formulas (φ → (ψ → φ)), ((φ → (ψ → χ)) → ((φ → ψ) → (φ → χ))), and ((¬φ → ¬ψ) → (ψ → φ));
  • for all formulas φ, ψ ∈ ForPL, R0 contains the rule ({φ, (φ → ψ)}, ψ).

As written, SF0 is not complete, because it only deals with formulas that contain symbols in BP ⋃ {→, ¬}. However, every formula is logically equivalent to a formula that only uses symbols in BP ⋃ {→, ¬}. The following rules can be added to ensure completeness, leading to the set of rules R+0:

propositional-logic.html: last modified 2020/05/06 14:55:42 by Antoine Zimmermann.